So we fix a theory in a language . A definable set is defined, in a given model of , by a formula. More precisely, we consider definable sets in cartesian powers of the model , which can be defined by a formula in free variables with parameters in some subset of . By definition, such a formula is a formula of the form , where is a formula in free variables, split into two groups and and is an -tuple of parameters; the formula can have quantifiers and bounded variables too. Given such a formula, we define a subset of by . We write for the set of all subsets of which are definable with parameters in .
Let us give examples, where is the language of rings and is the theory of algebraically closed fields:
- , given by the formula “” with 1 variable and parameter;
- , given by the formula “” with 1 free variable , and one bounded variable ;
- , where the model is the field of complex numbers, is the formula in 4 free variables, and the parameters are given by .
The reason behind this theorem is the following set-theoretic interpretation of quantifiers and logical connectors. Precisely, if is a formula in variables, and , the definable subset of coincides with the image of the definable subset of under the projection . Similarly, if and are two formulas in free variables, then the definable subset is the union of the definable subsets and . And if is a formula in variables, then the definable subset is the complement in of the definable subset .
For example, the subset defined above can also be defined by .
One says that the theory ACF admits elimination of quantifiers: modulo the axioms of algebraically closed fields, every formula of the language is equivalent to a formula without quantifiers.
An important consequence of this property is that for every extension of models of ACF, the theory of is equal to the theory of —one says that every extension of models is elementary.
Let be either or a prime number. Observe that every algebraically closed field of characteristic is an extension of if , or of if is a prime number. As a consequence, for every characteristic , the theory of algebraically closed fields of characteristic (defined by the axioms of , and the axiom that the characteristic is if is a prime number, or the infinite list of axioms that assert that the characteristic is , if ) is complete: this list of axioms determines everything that can be said about algebraically closed fields of characteristic .
Definition. — Let and let be a subset of . The type of (with parameters in ) is the set of all formulas in free variables with parameters in such that holds in the model .
Definition. — Let be a subset of . For every integer , the set of types (with parameters in ) is the set of all types , where is an extension of which is a model of and . One then says that this type is realized in .
Gödel's completeness theorem allows us to give an alternative description of . Namely, let be a set of formulas in free variables and parameters in which contains the diagram of (that is, all formulas which involve only elements of and are true in ). Assume that is consistent (there exists a model which is an extension of and and element such that holds in for every ) and maximal (for every formula , then for every model and every such that , then does not hold). Then .
For every formula in free variables and parameters in , let be the set of types such that . Then the subsets of consistute a basis of open sets for a natural topology on .
Theorem. — The topological space is compact and totally discontinuous.
Let us detail the case of the theory ACF in the langage of rings. I claim that if is a field, then is homeomorphic to the spectrum endowed with its constructible topology. Concretely, for every algebraically closed extension of and every , the homeomorphism maps to the prime ideal consisting of all polynomials such that .
A type is isolated if and only if the prime ideal is maximal. Consequently, if , there is exactly one non-isolated type in , corresponding to the generic point of the spectrum .
As for any compact topological space, a space of types can be studied via its Cantor-Bendixson analysis, which is a decreasing sequence of subspaces, indexed by ordinals, defined by transfinite induction. First of all, for every topological space , one denotes by the set of all non-isolated points of . One then defines , if is a successor-ordinal, and if is a limit-ordinal. For , the Cantor-Bendixson rank of is defined by if and for , and if for every ordinal . The set of points of infinite rank is the largest perfect subset of .
Let us return to the example of the theory ACF. If a type corresponds to a prime ideal of , its Cantor-Bendixson rank is the Zariski dimension of . More generally, if is a constructible subset of , then is the Zariski-dimension of the Zariski-closure of . Moreover, the points of maximal Cantor-Bendixson rank correspond to the generic points of the irreducible components of maximal dimension; in particular, there are only finitely many of them.
Definition. — One says that a theory is -stable if for every finite or countable set of parameters , the space of 1-types is finite or countable.
The theory ACF is -stable. Indeed, if is the field generated by , then being
a countable noetherian ring, it has only countably many prime ideals.
Since any non-empty perfect set is uncountable, one has the following lemma.
Lemma. — Let be an -stable theory and let be a model of . Then the Cantor-Bendixson rank of every type is finite.
Let us assume that is -stable and let be a closed subset of . Then is finite, and the set of points such that is finite and non-empty.
This example gives a strong indication that the model theory approach may be extremly fruitful for the study of algebraic theories whose geometry is not as well developed than algebraic geometry.
There seems to be a typo in the statement of Chevalley's theorem: "smallest boolean _algebra_ ..."
ReplyDeleteIndeed, thanks!
Delete