Showing posts with label math. Show all posts
Showing posts with label math. Show all posts

Saturday, March 29, 2025

A simple proof of a theorem of Kronecker

Kronecker's theorem of the title is the following.

Theorem.Let $\alpha\in\mathbf C$ be an algebraic integer all of whose conjugates have absolute value at most $1$. Then either $\alpha=0$, or $\alpha$ is a root of unity.

This theorem has several elementary proofs. In this post, I explain the simple proof proposed by Gebhart Greiter in his American Mathematical Monthly note, adding details so that it would (hopefully) be more accessible to students.

The possibility $\alpha=0$ is rather unentertaining, hence let us assume that $\alpha\neq0$.

Let us first analyse the hypothesis. The assumption that $\alpha$ is an algebraic integer means that there exists a monic polynomial $f\in\mathbf Z[T]$ such that $f(\alpha)=0$. I claim that $f$ can be assumed to be irreducible in $\mathbf Q[T]$; it is then the minimal polynomial of $\alpha$. This follows from Gauss's theorem, and let me give a proof for that. Let $g\in \mathbf Q[T]$ be a monic irreducible factor of $f$ and let $h\in\mathbf Q[T]$ such that $f=gh$. Chasing denominators and dividing out by their gcd, there are polynomials $g_1,h_1\in\mathbf Z[T]$ whose coefficients are mutually coprime, and natural integers $u,v$ such that $g=ug_1$ and $h=vh_1$. Then $(uv)f=g_1 h_1$. Since $f$ is monic, this implies that $uv$ is an integer. Let us prove that $uv=1$; otherwise, it has a prime factor $p$. Considering the relation $(uv)f=g_1h_1$ modulo $p$ gives $0=g_1 h_1 \pmod p$. Since their coefficients are mutually coprime, the polynomials $g_1$ and $h_1$ are nonzero modulo $p$, hence their product is nonzero. This is a contradiction.

So we have a monic polynomial $f\in\mathbf Z[T]$, irreducible in $\mathbf Q[T]$, such that $f(\alpha)=0$. That is to say, $f$ is the minimal polynomial of $\alpha$, so that the conjugates of $\alpha$ are the roots of $f$. Note that the roots of $f$ are pairwise distinct — otherwise, the $\gcd(f,f')$ would be a nontrivial factor of $f$. Moreover, $0$ is not a root of $f$, for otherwhise one could factor $f=T\cdot f_1$.

Let us now consider the companion matrix to $f$: writing $f=T^n+c_1T^{n-1}+\dots+c_n$, so that $n=\deg(f)$, this is the matrix \[ C_f = \begin{pmatrix} 0 & \dots & 0 & -c_n \\ 1 & \ddots & \vdots & -c_{n-1} \\ 0 & \ddots & & -c_{n-2} \\ 0 & \cdots & 1 & -c_1 \end{pmatrix}.\] If $e_1,\ldots,e_n$ are the canonical column vectors $e_1=(1,0,\dots,0)$, etc., then $C_f\cdot e_1=e_2$, \ldots, $C_f \cdot e_{n-1}=e_{n}$, and $C_f\cdot e_n = -c_{n} e_1-\dots -c_1 e_n$. Consequently, \[ f(C_f)\cdot e_1 = C_f^n\cdot e_1 +c_1 C_f^{n_1} \cdot e_1+ \dots +c_n e_1 = 0.\] Moreover, for $2\leq k\leq n$, one has $f(C_f)\cdot e_k=f(C_f)\cdot C_f^{k-1}\cdot e_1=C_f^{k-1}\cdot f(C_f)\cdot e_1=0$. Consequently, $f(C_f)=0$ and the complex eigenvalues of $f(C_f)$ are roots of $f$. Since $f$ has simple roots, $C_f$ is diagonalizable and their exists a matrix $P\in\mathrm{GL}(n,\mathbf C)$ and diagonal matrix $D$ such that $C_f=P\cdot D\cdot P^{-1}$, the diagonal entries of $D$ are roots of $f$. Since $0$ is not a root of $f$, the matrix $D$ is invertible, and $C_f$ is invertible as well. More precisely, one can infer from the definition of $C_f$ that $g(C_f)\cdot e_1\neq 0$ for any nonzero polynomial $g$ of degre $<n$, so that $f$ is the minimal polynomial of $C_f$. Consequently, all of its roots are actually eigenvalues of $C_f$, and appear in $D$; in particular, $\alpha$ is an eigenvalue of $C_f$.

For every $k\geq 1$, one has $C_f^k=P\cdot (D^k)\cdot P^{-1}$. Since all entries of $D$ have absolute value at most $1,$ the set of all $D^k$ is bounded in $\mathrm{M}_n(\mathbf C)$. Consequently, the set $\{C_f^k\,;\, k\in\mathbf Z\}$ is bounded in $\mathrm M_n(\mathbf C)$. On the other hand, this set consists in matrices in $\mathrm M_n(\mathbf Z)$. It follows that this set is finite.

There are integers $k$ and $\ell$ such that $k< \ell$ and $C_f^k=C_f^\ell$. Since $C_f$ is invertible, one has $C_f^{\ell-k}=1$. Since $\alpha$ is an eigenvalue of $C_f,$ this implies $\alpha^{\ell-k}=1$. We thus have proved that $\alpha$ is a root of unity.

Saturday, January 11, 2025

On numbers and unicorns

Reading a book on philosophy of mathematics, even if it's written lightly, such as that one, Why is there philosophy of mathematics at all? by Ian Hacking, may have unexpected effects. The most visible one has been a poll that I submitted on Mastodon on December 4th. As you can read, there were four options:

  • Numbers exist
  • Unicorns exist
  • Numbers have more existence than unicorns
  • Neither numbers no unicorns exist

As you can see, three main options each share a rough third of the votes, the existence of unicorns being favored by a small 4% of the 142 participants.

Post by @antoinechambertloir@mathstodon.xyz
View on Mastodon

In this post, I would like to discuss these four options, from the point of view of a mathematician with a limited expertise on philosophy. Funnily, each of them, including the second one, has some substance. Moreover, it will become apparent at the end that the defense of any of those options relies on the meaning we give to the word exist.

Numbers exist

We have traces of numbers as old as we have traces of writing. The Babylonian clay tablet known as “Plimpton 322” dates from 1800 BC and mentions Pythagorean triples (triples of integers $(a,b,c)$ such $a^2=b^2+c^2$) written in the sexagesimal (base 60) writing of Babylonians. More than 1000 years later, Pythagoras and his school wished to explain everything in the world using numbers, usually depicted geometrically, drawing pebbles arranged in triangles, squares, rectangles and even pentagons. Musical harmony was based on specific numerical ratios. Plato's writings are full of references to mathematics, and a few specific numbers, such as 5040, are even given a political relevance. Even earlier, the Chinese I Ching based predictions on random numbers.

Euclid's Elements give us an account of numbers that still sounds quite modern. A great part of elementary arithmetic can be found there: divisibility, the “Euclidean algorithm”, prime numbers and the fact that there are infinitely many of them or, more precisely, that there are more prime numbers than any given magnitude. On the other hand, it is worth saying that Euclid's concept of number doesn't exactly fit with our modern concept: since “A number is a multitude composed of units”, numbers are whole numbers, and it is implicit that that zero is not a number, and neither is one. Moreover, proposition 21 of book 10, which we read as proving the irrationality of the square root of 2, is not a statement about a hypothetical number called “square root of 2”, but the fact that the diagonal of a square of unit length is irrational, ie, not commensurable with the unit length.

History went on and on and numbers gradually were prevalent in modern societies. Deciding the exact date of Easter in a ill-connected Christian world led to the necessity of computing it, using an algorithm known as computus, and the name happened to be used for every calculation. The development of trade led to the development of computing devices, abacus, counting boards (the counter at your prefered shop is the place where the counting board was laid), and Simon Stevin's De Thiende explicitly motivates trade as an application of his book on decimal fractions.

Needless to say, our digital age is litteraly infused with numbers.

Unicorns exist

Traces of unicorns can be found by the Indus valley. The animal seems to have disappeared but the Greeks thought they lived in India. In Western Europe, Middle ages tapestry gives numerous wonderful representations of unicorns, such as the Paris Dame à la licorne. This extract from Umberto Eco's The name of the rose gives additional proof of their existence:

“But is the unicorn a falsehood? It’s the sweetest of animals and a noble symbol. It stands for Christ, and for chastity; it can be captured only by setting a virgin in the forest, so that the animal, catching her most chaste odor, will go and lay its head in her lap, offering itself as prey to the hunters’ snares.”
“So it is said, Adso. But many tend to believe that it’s a fable, an invention of the pagans.”
“What a disappointment,” I said. “I would have liked to encounter one, crossing a wood. Otherwise what’s the pleasure of crossing a wood?”

The Internet age gave even more evidence to the existence of unicorns. For example, we now know that though it is not rainbowish, contrary to a well-spread myth, unicorns have a colorful poop.

Numbers have more existence than unicorns

Whatever numbers and unicorns could be, we are litteraly surrounded by the former, and have scarce traces of the latter. I'd also like to add that numbers have a big impact in all modern human activities: the most basic trading activities use numbers, as does the most sophisticated science. But we don't need to wish to send a man to the moon to require numbers: the political life is build around votations and polls, all timed schedules are expressed in numbers, and schools, hospitals, movies are regularly ranked or assigned rates. An example given by Hacking is the existence of world records for, say, 50 m free stroke swimming. That requires good swimmers, of course, but also elaborate timers, very precise measurement tools to have the swimming pool acknowledged as a legitimate place, and so on. On the other hand, how nice the cultural or artistic representations of unicorns can be, they don't have that prevalence in the modern world, and it is rare that something is possible because of something involving unicorns.

Neither numbers nor unicorns exist

This is probably my favorite take, and that's maybe slightly bizarre from a mathematician, especially one versed in number theory. But give some lucid look at the discourse that we have about numbers. On one side, we have the famous quote of Leopold Kronecker, “Die ganzen Zahlen hat der liebe Gott gemacht, alles andere ist Menschenwerk.” — God made whole numbers, all the rest is the work of man. Does this mean that at least some numbers, the natural integers, exist in the world in the same way that we can find water, iron, gold or grass? Are there number mines somewhere? It doesn't seem so, and I'm inclined to say that if numbers exist, they also are the creation of mankind. The ZFC axioms of set theory postulate the existence of some set $\mathbf N$ satisfying an induction principle, and that induction principle is used to endow that set with an addition and a multiplication which make it a mathematical model of Kronecker's “whole numbers”, but does this mean that numbers exist? After all, what does guarantee that the ZFC axioms are not self contradictory? And if they were, would that mean that whole numbers cease to exist? Certainly not. In any case, our daily use of whole numbers would not be the least disturbed by a potential contradiction in those axioms. But that indicates that being able to speak of integers withing the ZFC set theory doesn't confer those integers some existence, in the same sense that grass, water, iron exist. Another indication of their elusive character is the way mathematicians or computer scientists pretend numbers are specific objects, such as zero being the empty set, 1 being the set $\{\emptyset\}$, and, more generally, the integer $n+1$ being $n \cup \{n\}$. This is at most a functional fiction, as is well explained by Benacerraf (1965) in his paper, “What numbers could not be” (The Philosophical Review, Vol. 74, No. 1, pp. 47-73).

But all in all, everything is fine, because whether numbers (resp. unicorns) exist or don't, we, humans, have developed a language to talk about them, make us think, make us elaborate new works of art or of science, and after all, this is all that counts, isn't it?

Monday, August 12, 2024

Combinatorics of partitions

Divided powers are an algebraic gadget that emulate, in an arbitrary ring, the functions $x\mapsto x^n/n!$ for all integers $n$, together with the natural functional equations that they satisfy. 

One of them is a nice binomial theorem without binomial coefficients : denoting $x^n/n!$ by $x^{[n]}$, one has $$ (x+y)^{[n]}=\sum_{k=0}^n x^{[n-k]} y^{[k]}. $$ 

Another formula looks at what happens when one iterates the construction: if everything happens nicely, one has $$ (x^{[n]})^{[m]}=\frac1{m!}\left(x^n/n!\right)^m = \frac1{(n!)^m m!} x^{nm} = \frac{(mn)!}{m! n!^m} x^{[mn]}. $$ 

 In the development of the theory, the remark that comes then is the necessary observation that the coefficient $(mn)!/{m! n!^m}$ is an integer, which is not obvious since it is written as a fraction. Two arguments are given to justify this fact. 

  1. The formula $$ \frac{(mn)!}{m! n!^m} = \prod_{k=1}^{m} \binom{k n-1}{n-1} $$ which the authors claim can be proved by induction
  2. The observation that $(mn)!/m!n!^m$ is the number of (unordered) partitions of a set with $mn$ elements into $m$ subsets with $n$ elements.

The latter fact is a particular case of a more general counting question: if $n=(n_1,\dots,n_r)$ are integers and $N=n_1+\dots+n_r$, then the number of (unordered) partitions of a set with $N$ elements into subsets of cardinalities $n_1,\dots,n_r$ is equal to $$\frac{N!}{\prod n_i! \prod_{k>0} m_k(n)!},$$ where $m_k(n)$ is the number of occurences of $k$ in the sequence $(n_1,\dots,n_r)$. 

The goal of this blog post is to present a combinatorial argument for the first equality, and an alternative expression of the second number as a product of integers. We also give a formal, group theoretical proof, that this quotient of factorials solves the given counting problem. 

 $\gdef\abs#1{\lvert#1\rvert}$ $\gdef\Card{\operatorname{Card}}$  

Counting partitions of given type 

 Let $S$ be a set with $N$ elements. A partition of $S$ is a subset $\{s_1,\dots,s_r\}$ of $\mathfrak P(S)$ consisting of nonempty, pairwise disjoint, subsets whose union is $S$. Its *type* is the “multiset” of integers given by their cardinalities. Because no $s_i$ is empty, the type is a multiset of nonzero integers. It is slightly easier to authorize zero in this type; then a partition has to be considered as a multiset of subsets of $S$, still assumed pairwise disjoint, so that only the empty subset can be repeated.

The group $G$ of permutations of $S$ acts on the set $\Pi_S$ of partitions of $S$. This action preserves the type of a partition, so that we get an action on the set $\Pi_{S,n}$ on the set of partitions of type $n$, of any multiset of integers $n$. It is nonempty if and only if $\abs n=N$.

This action is transitive: Given two partitions $(s_1,\dots,s_r)$ and $(t_1,\dots t_r)$ with the same type $(n_1,\dots,n_r)$, numbered so that $\abs{s_i}=\abs{t_i}={n_i}$ for all $i$, we just define a permutation of $S$ that maps the elements of $s_i$ to $t_i$.

By the orbit-stabilizer theorem, the number of partitions of type $n$ is equal to $\Card(G)/\Card(G_s)$, where $G_s$ is the stabilizer of any partition $s$ of type $n$. Since $\Card(S)=N$, one has $\Card(G)=N!=\abs n!$.

On the other hand, the stabilizer $G_s$ of a partition $(s_1,\dots,s_r)$ can be described as follows. By an element $g$ of this stabilizer, the elements of $s_i$ are mapped to some set $s_j$ which has the same cardinality as $s_i$. In other words, there is a morphism of groups from $G_s$ to the subgroup of the symmetric group $\mathfrak S_r$ consisting of permutations that preserve the cardinality. This subgroup is a product of symmetric groups $\mathfrak S_{m_k}$, for all $k> 0$, where $m_k$ is the number of occurrences of $k$ in $(n_1,\dots,n_r)$. Here, we omit the factor corresponding to $k=0$ because our morphism doesnt' see it.

This morphism is surjective, because it has a section. Given a permutation $\sigma$ of $\{1,\dots,r\}$ that preserves the cardinalities, we have essentially shown above how to construct a permutation of $S$ that induces $\sigma$, and this permutation belongs to $G_s$. More precisely, if we number the elements of $s_i$ as $(x_{i,1},\dots,x_{i,n_i})$, we lift $\sigma$ to the permutation that maps $x_{i,j}$ to $x_{\sigma(i),j}$ for all $i,j$. This makes sense since $n_{i}=n_{\sigma(i)}$ for all $i$.

The kernel of this morphism $G_s\to \prod_{k>0} \mathfrak S_{m_k}$ consists of permutations that fix each $s_i$. It is clearly equal to the product of the symmetric groups $\prod \mathfrak S_{n_i}$.

One thus has $\Card(G_s)=\prod n_i! \prod_{k>0} m_k!$, as was to be shown.

A combinatorial interpretation of the first relation


As we said above, that relation $$ \frac{(mn)!}{m^ n!^m} = \prod_{k=1}^{m-1} \binom{kn-1}{n-1} $$ can be proved by induction, just playing with factorials, but we want a combinatorial interpretation for it. (Here we assume that $n\geq 1$.)
By the preceding paragraph, the left hand side is the number of partitions of a set with $mn$ elements of type $(n,\dots,n)$. We may assume that this set is numbered $\{1,\dots,mn\}$.

Such a partition can be defined as follows. First, we choose the subset that contains $1$: this amounts to choosing $n-1$ elements among $\{2,\dots,mn\}$, and there are $\binom{mn-1}{n-1}$ possibilities. Now, we have to choose the subset that contains the smallest element which is not in the first chosen subset. There are $n-1$ elements to choose among the remaining $mn-n-1=(m-1)n-1$ ones, hence $\binom{(m-1)n-1}{n-1}$ possibilities. And we go on in the same way, until we have chosen the $m$ required subsets. (For the last one, there is course only one such choice, and notice that the last factor is $\binom{n-1}{n-1}=1$.)

An integral formula for the number of partitions of given type


Finally, we wish to give an alternating formula for the number of partitions of given type of a set $S$ that makes it clear that it is an integer. Again, we can assume that the set $S$ is equal to $\{1,\dots,N\}$ and that $n=(n_1,\dots,n_r)$ is a multiset of integers such that $\abs n=N$.

Let us write $n$ in an other way, $n=(0^{m_0},1^{m_1},\dots)$, meaning that $0$ is repeated $m_0$ times, $1$ is repeated $m_1$ times, etc. One has $N=\sum k m_k$. The idea is that we can first partition $S$ into a subsets of cardinalities $m_1$, $2m_2$,… and then subpartition these subsets: the first one into $m_1$ subsets with one element, the second into $m_2$ subsets with two elements, etc.

The number of ordered partitions with $m_1$, $2m_2$… elements is the multinomial number $$ \binom{N}{m_1,2m_2,\dots}.$$ And the other choice is the product of integers as given in the preceding section. This gives $$ \frac{\abs n!}{\prod_i n_i! \prod_{k>0}m_k(n)!} = \binom{N}{m_1,2m_2,\dots}\prod_{k>0} \frac{(km_k)!}{k!^{m_k} m_k(n)!}.$$ We can also write the fractions that appear in the product as integers: $$ \frac{\abs n!}{\prod_i n_i! \prod_{k>0}m_k(n)!} =\binom{N}{m_1,2m_2,\dots} \prod_{k>0} \prod_{m=1}^{m_k} \binom {km-1}{k-1}.$$

Tuesday, December 22, 2020

Celebrating Ramanujan's birthday — From powers of divisors to coefficients of modular forms

In a Twitter post, Anton Hilado reminded us that today (December 22nd) was the birthday of Srinivasa Ramanujan, and suggested somebody explains the “Ramanujan conjectures”. The following blog post is an attempt at an informal account. Or, as @tjf frames it, my christmas present to math twitter.

The story begins 1916, in a paper Ramanujan published in the Transactions of the Cambridge Philosophical Society, under the not so explicit title: On certain arithmetical functions. His goal started as the investigation of the sum $\sigma_s(n)$ of all $s$th powers of all divisors of an integer $n$, and approximate functional equations of the form
\[ \sigma_r(0)\sigma_s(n)+\sigma_r(1)\sigma_s(n-1)+\dots+\sigma_r(n)\sigma_s(0)
\approx \frac{\Gamma(r+1)\Gamma(s+1)}{\Gamma(r+s+2)} \frac{\zeta(r+1)\zeta(s+1)}{\zeta(r+s+2)}\sigma_{r+s+1}(n) + \frac{\zeta(1-r)+\zeta(1-s)}{r+s} n \sigma_{r+s-1}(n), \]
where $\sigma_s(0)=\dfrac12 \zeta(-s)$, and $\zeta$ is Riemann's zeta function. In what follows, $r,s$ will be positive odd integers, so that $\sigma_s(0)$ is half the value of Riemann's zeta function at a negative odd integer; it is known to be a rational number, namely $(-1)^sB_{s+1}/2(s+1)$, where $B_{s+1}$ is the $(s+1)$th Bernoulli number.

This investigation, in which Ramanujan engages without giving any motivation, quickly leads him to the introduction of infinite series,
\[ S_r = \frac12 \zeta(-r) + \frac{1^rx}{1-x}+\frac{2^r x^2}{1-x^2}+\frac{3^rx^3}{1-x^3}+\dots. \]
Nowadays, the parameter $x$ would be written $q$, and $S_r=\frac12 \zeta(-r) E_{r+1}$, at least if $r$ is an odd integer, $E_r$ being the Fourier expansion of the Eisenstein series of weight $r$. The particular cases $r=1,3,5$ are given special names, namely $P,Q,R$, and Ramanujan proves that $S_s$ is a linear combination of $Q^mR^n$, for integers $m,n$ such that $4m+6n=s+1$. Nowadays, we understand this as the fact that $Q$ and $R$ generated the algebra of modular forms—for the full modular group $\mathrm{SL}(2,\mathbf Z)$.

In the same paper, Ramanujan spells out the system of algebraic differential equations satisfied by $P,Q,R$:
\[ x \frac {dP}{dx} = \frac{1}{12}(P^2-Q),  x\frac{dQ}{dx}=\frac13(PQ-R), x\frac{dR}{dx}=\frac12(PR-Q^2). \]

The difference of the two sides of the initial equation has an expansion as a linear combination of $Q^mR^n$, where $4m+6n=r+s+2$. By the functional equation of Riemann's zeta function, relating $\zeta(s)$ and $\zeta(1-s)$, this expression vanishes for $x=0$, hence there is a factor $Q^3-R^2$.

Ramanujan then notes that

$ x\frac{d}{dx} \log(Q^3-R^2)=P$, so that

\[  P =x\frac{d}{dx} \log \left( x\big((1-x)(1-x^2)(1-x^3)\dots\big)^{24} \right) \]

and 

\[ Q^3-R^2 = 1728 x  \big((1-x)(1-x^2)(1-x^3)\dots\big)^{24}= \sum \tau(n) x^n, \]
an expression now known as Ramanujan's $\Delta$-function. In fact, Ramanujan also makes the relation with elliptic functions, in particular, with Weierstrass's $\wp$-function. Then, $\Delta$ corresponds to the discriminant of the degree 3 polynomial $f$ such that $\wp'(u)^2=f(\wp(u))$. 

In any case, factoring $Q^3-R^2$ in the difference of the two terms, it is written as a linear combination of $Q^mR^n$, where $4m+6n=r+s-10$. When $r$ and $s$ are positive odd integers such that $r+s\leq 12$, there are no such pairs $(m,n)$, hence the difference vanishes, and Ramanujan obtains an equality in these cases. 

Ramanujan is interested in the quality of the initial approximation. He finds an upper bound of the form $\mathrm O(n^{\frac23(r+s+1)})$. Using Hardy–Littlewood's method, he shows that it cannot be smaller than $n^{\frac12(r+s)}$. That prompts his interest for the size of the coefficients of arithmetical functions, and $Q^3-R^2$ is the simplest one. He computes the coefficients $\tau(n)$ for $n\leq30$ and gives them in a table:

Recalling that $\tau(n)$ is $\mathrm O(n^7)$, and not $\mathrm O(n^5)$, Ramanujan states that there is reason to believe that $\tau(n)=\mathrm O(n^{\frac{11}2+\epsilon})$ but not $\mathrm O(n^{\frac{11}2})$. That this holds is Ramanujan's conjecture.

Ramanujan was led to believe this by observing that the Dirichlet series $ \sum \frac{\tau(n)}{n^s} $ factors as an infinite product (“Euler product”, would we say), indexed by the prime numbers:

\[ \sum_{n=1}^\infty \frac{\tau(n)}{n^s} = \prod_p \frac{1}{1-\tau(p)p^{-s}+p^{11-2s}}. \]

This would imply that $\tau$ is a multiplicative function: $\tau(mn )=\tau(m)\tau(n)$ if $m$ and $n$ are coprime, as well as the more complicated relation $\tau(p^{k+2})=\tau(p)\tau(p^{k+1})-p^{11}\tau(p^k)$ between the $\tau(p^k)$. These relations have been proved by Louis Mordell in 1917. He introduced operators (now called Hecke operators) $T_p$ (indexed by prime numbers $p$) on the algebra of modular functions and proved that Ramanujan's $\Delta$-function is an eigenfunction. (It has little merit for that, because it is alone in its weight, so that $T_p \Delta$ is a multiple of $\Delta$, necessarily $T_p\Delta=\tau(p)\Delta$.)

The bound $\lvert{\tau(p)}\rvert\leq p^{11/2}$ means that the polynomial $1-\tau(p) X+p^{11}X^2$ has two complex conjugate roots. This part of the conjecture would be proved in 1973 only, by Pierre Deligne, and required many additional ideas. One was conjectures of Weil about the number of points of algebraic varieties over finite fields, proved by Deligne in 1973, building on Grothendieck's étale cohomology. Another was the insight (due to Michio Kuga, Mikio Sato and Goro Shimura) that Ramanujan's conjecture could be reframed as an instance of the Weil conjectures, and its actual proof by Deligne in 1968, applied to the 10th symmetric product of the universal elliptic curve.